Daniel Jacobson
Bowling Green State University
Network
Latest external collaboration on country level. Dive into details by clicking on the dots.
Publication
Featured researches published by Daniel Jacobson.
The Philosophical Review | 2008
Daniel Jacobson
In this essay I will argue, flouting paradox, that Mill was a utilitarian but not a consequentialist. According to the textbook definition, of course, utilitarianism just is the combination of a certain sort of theory of the good (as pleasure, happiness, or flourishing) and a consequentialist theory of the right. My conclusion thus seems necessarily false. Nevertheless, the argument will proceed in two stages. First, I argue that there is logical space for a view that deserves to be called utilitarian despite its rejection of consequentialism. Then I argue that this position was in fact occupied by the most renowned utilitarian, John Stuart Mill. The first step in my argument rests on what might be considered a clever trick, at best; but this is to be expected when one argues for a claim that seems necessarily false. I concede from the beginning, though, that were my conclusion merely a semantic or conceptual point, this argument would be of little interest. But the conclusion is quite interesting because the tricky step in the argument exposes an implicit feature of consequentialism that is both substantive and dubious and has received inadequate attention. Examination of this implicit assumption will reveal an important contrast between consequentialism and its
Legal Theory | 2001
Daniel Jacobson
The fundamental tenet of the liberal conception of free speech is the principle of content neutrality, which Mill espoused in claiming that “there ought to exist the fullest liberty of professing and discussing, as a matter of ethical conviction, any doctrine, however immoral it may be considered.” 1. J.S. M ILL , O N L IBERTY 36, n. 1 (John Gray and G.W. Smith eds., Routledge 1991) (1859). Note that content-neutrality as a principle of free speech is a different and less ambitious principle from neutrality among conceptions of the good. On this view, the immorality, the falsity, and even the harmfulness of an opinion are not good reasons to censor it. “However positive any one’s persuasion may be, not only of the falsity but of the pernicious consequences” of an opinion, Mill writes, its expression cannot legitimately be prohibited. 2. Id . at 43. I am claiming that Mill does not consider harm prevention per se to be even a good (much less a sufficient) reason to censor an opinion or sentiment. This claim is admittedly in tension with some glosses of the so-called harm principle; but, as I have argued elsewhere, the role and content of Mill’s principle of liberty is often fundamentally misconstrued. See Daniel Jacobson, Mill on Liberty, Speech, and the Free Society , 29 P HIL . & P UB . A FF . 276 (2000). Nevertheless, in certain limited circumstances, particular acts of assertion or expression must “lose their immunity” from interference, as Mill puts it, so that we may proscribe incitement to riot, harassment, and the like. Just how to specify those circumstances consistently with content neutrality is a challenge for the liberal program. Of course, this principle and the liberal conception of free speech it embodies are controversial. It can be questioned whether the principle succeeds in protecting the class of speech and other expression that liberals aspire to protect. And even if it does cover the right class, the principle’s justification can be doubted. But I will not discuss these issues, on which there is already an immense literature, any further here.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research | 2000
Justin D'Arms; Daniel Jacobson
Ethics | 2000
Justin D'Arms; Daniel Jacobson
Philosophical Topics | 1997
Daniel Jacobson
Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement | 2003
Justin D'Arms; Daniel Jacobson
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice | 2005
Daniel Jacobson
Archive | 2007
Justin D'Arms; Daniel Jacobson
Philosophy & Public Affairs | 1995
Daniel Jacobson
Archive | 2006
Daniel Jacobson; Justin D'Arms