Network


Latest external collaboration on country level. Dive into details by clicking on the dots.

Hotspot


Dive into the research topics where David Vander Laan is active.

Publication


Featured researches published by David Vander Laan.


Archive | 2006

Knowledge and reality

Thomas M. Crisp; Matthew Davidson; David Vander Laan

objects. What might the nominalist say in reply? The most plausible reply open to the nominalist seems to me to be along the following lines. My platonist critic is certainly a very literal-minded fellow. I didn’t mean the ‘some’ in the open sentence ‘x is like y in some anatomically relevant ways’ to be taken as a quantifier: I didn’t mean this sentence to be read ‘∃z (z is a way in which a thing can be like a thing and z is anatomical and x is like y in z)’. That’s absurd. One might as well read ‘There’s more than one way to skin a cat’ as ‘∃x ∃y (x is a way of skinning a cat and y is a way of skinning a cat and x y)’. I meant this open sentence to have no internal logical structure, or none beyond that implied by the statement that two variables are free in it. It’s just a form of words we learn to use by comparing various pairs of objects in the ordinary business of life. And here is the rejoinder to this reply: If you take that line you confront problems it would be better not to have to confront. Consider the sentence ‘x is like y in some physiologically relevant ways’. Surely there is some logical or structural or syntactical 20 Peter van Inwagen relation between this sentence and ‘x is like y in some anatomically relevant ways’? One way to explain the relation between these two sentences is to read the former as ‘∃z (z is a way in which a thing can be like a thing and z is physiological and x is like y in z)’ and the latter as ‘∃z (z is a way in which a thing can be like a thing and z is anatomical and x is like y in z)’. How would you explain it? Or how would you explain the relation between the sentences ‘x is like y in some anatomically relevant ways’ (which you say has no logical structure) and ‘x is like y in all anatomically relevant ways’? If neither of these sentences has a logical structure, how do you account for the obvious validity of the argument Either of two female spiders of the same species is like the other in all anatomically relevant ways. Hence, an insect that is like a given female spider in some anatomically relevant ways is like any female spider of the same species in some anatomically relevant ways? If the premise and conclusion of this argument are read as having the logical structure their syntax suggests, the validity of this argument is easily demonstrable in textbook quantifier logic. If one insists that they have no logical structure, one will find it difficult to account for the validity of this argument. That is one of those problems I alluded to, one of those problems it would be better not to have to confront. (One of thousands of such problems.) I suggest that we can learn a lesson from this little exchange between an imaginary nominalist and an imaginary platonist: that one should accept the following condition of adequacy on philosophical paraphrases. Paraphrases must not be such as to leave us without an account of the logical relations between predicates that are obviously logically related. Essentially the same constraint on paraphrase can be put in these words: A paraphrase must not leave us without an account of the validity of any obviously valid argument. Accepting this constraint has, I believe, a significant consequence. This consequence requires a rather lengthy statement. Apparent quantification over properties pervades our discourse. In the end, one can avoid quantifying over properties only by quantifying over other sorts of abstract object—”ways in which a thing can be like a thing,” for example. But most philosophers, if forced to chose between quantifying over properties and quantifying over these other objects


Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic | 1997

The Ontology of Impossible Worlds

David Vander Laan

The best arguments for possible worlds as states of affairs furnish us with equally good arguments for impossible worlds of the same sort. I argue for a theory of impossible worlds on which the impossible worlds correspond to maximal inconsistent classes of propositions. Three objections are rejected. In the final part of the paper, I present a menu of impossible worlds and explore some of their interesting formal properties.


Religious Studies | 2006

Persistence and divine conservation

David Vander Laan

Plausibly, if an object persists through time, then its later existence must be caused by its earlier existence. Many theists endorse a theory of continuous creation, according to which God is the sole cause of a creatures existence at a given time. The conjunction of these two theses rather unfortunately implies that no object distinct from God persists at all. What strategies for resolving this difficulty are available?


Australasian Journal of Philosophy | 2010

A Relevance Constraint on Composition

David Vander Laan

Whether certain objects compose a whole at a given time does not seem to depend on anything other than the character of those objects and the relations between them. This observation suggests a far-reaching constraint on theories of composition. One version of the constraint has been explicitly adopted by van Inwagen and rules out his own answer to the composition question. The constraint also rules out the other well-known moderate answers that have so far been proposed.Whether certain objects compose a whole at a given time does not seem to depend on anything other than the character of those objects and the relations between them. This observation suggests a far-reaching constraint on theories of composition. One version of the constraint has been explicitly adopted by van Inwagen and rules out his own answer to the composition question. The constraint also rules out the other well-known moderate answers that have so far been proposed.


Faith and Philosophy | 2018

The Paradox of the End without End

David Vander Laan

In much of Christian thought humans are taken to have an ultimate end, understood as the highest attainable good. Christians also anticipate “the life everlasting.” Together these ideas generate a paradox. If the end can be reached in a finite amount of time, some longer-lasting state will be better still, so the purported end is not the highest good after all. But if the end is to possess some good forever, then it will never be reached. So it seems an everlasting being cannot have an ultimate end—a conclusion that apparently makes human life pointless. How can the paradox be solved?


Archive | 2006

Knowledge and reality : essays in honor of Alvin Plantinga

Thomas M. Crisp; Matthew Davidson; David Vander Laan


Philosophical Studies | 2001

A regress argument for restrictive incompatibilism

David Vander Laan


Archive | 2007

Creation and Conservation

Jonathan Kvanvig; David Vander Laan


Faith and Philosophy | 2007

THE SANCTIFICATION ARGUMENT FOR PURGATORY

David Vander Laan


Analysis | 2015

The Concord of Molinism with Modal Voluntarism

David Vander Laan

Collaboration


Dive into the David Vander Laan's collaboration.

Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Matthew Davidson

California State University

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Researchain Logo
Decentralizing Knowledge