Network


Latest external collaboration on country level. Dive into details by clicking on the dots.

Hotspot


Dive into the research topics where Jacqueline Taylor is active.

Publication


Featured researches published by Jacqueline Taylor.


Archive | 1993

Hume's new science of the mind

John Biro; David Fate Norton; Jacqueline Taylor

“Human Nature is the only science of man.” T 1.4.7.14 For Hume, understanding the workings of the mind is the key to understanding everything else. There is a sense, therefore, in which to write about Humes philosophy of mind is to write about all of his philosophy. With that said, I shall nonetheless focus here on those specific doctrines that belong to what we today call the philosophy of mind, given our somewhat narrower conception of that subject. It should also be remembered that Hume describes his inquiry into the nature and workings of the mind as a science. This is an important clue to understanding both the goals and the results of that inquiry, as well as the methods Hume uses in pursuing it. As we will see, there is a thread running from Humes project of founding a science of the mind to that of the so-called cognitive sciences of the late twentieth century. For both, the study of the mind is in important respects just like the study of any other natural phenomenon. While it would be an overstatement to say that Humes entire interest lies in the construction of a science in this sense - he has other, more traditionally “philosophical,” concerns - recognizing the centrality of this scientific aim is essential for understanding him.


Archive | 2015

Reflecting subjects : passion, sympathy, and society in Hume's philosophy

Jacqueline Taylor

1. Experimenting with the Passions 2. Toward a Humean Social Theory: Sympathy, Belief, and Pride 3. Power and the Philosophy of Our Passions 4. Moral Authority and Moral Competence 5. The Dangers and Dignity of Pride 6. Humanity and the Dignity of Human Nature


Archive | 1993

An introduction to Hume's thought

David Fate Norton; Jacqueline Taylor

Much of what David Hume said about a wide range of subjects remains of great importance today. In the first volume of his first work, A Treatise of Human Nature, a work in which he articulated a new “science of human nature,” Hume focused on an interrelated set of issues in theory of knowledge, metaphysics, and philosophical psychology. More particularly, he explained how it is that we form such important conceptions as space and time, cause and effect, external objects, and personal identity. At the same time, he offered an equally important account of how or why we believe in the objects of these conceptions - an account of why we believe that causes are necessarily connected to effects, that there are enduring external objects, and that there are enduring selves - even though the human mind is unable to provide a satisfactory proof that these phenomena exist. In the second volume of the Treatise Hume expanded his account of human psychology, focusing on the origin and role of the passions and the nature of human freedom. In the third and final volume of this work he explored the origins and nature of morality. In later works he returned to many of these philosophical issues, but he also made substantial contributions to our understanding of political theory, aesthetics, economics, and philosophy of religion. In addition, he wrote an influential, six-volume History of England, a work published in over 175 editions in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, and still in print.


The Journal of Ethics | 2002

Hume on the Standard of Virtue

Jacqueline Taylor

Among those sympathetic to Humesmoral philosophy, a general consensus hasemerged that his first work on the topic,A Treatise of Human Nature, is his best. Hislater work, An Enquiry Concerning thePrinciples of Morals, is regarded as scaleddown in both scope and ambition. In contrastto this standard view, I argue that Humeslater work offers a more sophisticated theoryof moral evaluation. I begin by reviewing theTreatise theory of moral evaluation tohighlight the reasons why commentators find socompelling Humes account of the corrections wemake to our moral sentiments. The method isendorsed by philosophers such as Henry DavidAiken and Annette C. Baier because, theyallege, it shows that moral sentiments reflecta process of judgment that includes thepossibility of corrigibility and ofjustification. But Humes method of correctionfalls short and does not establish why thesentiments conforming to the standard of virtueshould count as moral judgments. In the secondEnquiry, Hume lays out a different set ofcriteria, including not only the need forcertain virtues of good judgment but attentionto the particular cultural and historicalorigins of the norms governing the virtues ofgood judgment. Humes attention to diversityin evaluative outlook in his more matureposition takes seriously the relation betweenmoral authority and public debate.


Archive | 2008

Hume’s Theory of Space and Time in Its Skeptical Context

Donald L. M. Baxter; David Fate Norton; Jacqueline Taylor

In Treatise 1.2, Of the ideas of space and time, Hume examines our ideas of spatial extension and temporal duration, our ideas of geometric equality, straightness, flatness, and mathematical point, and our ideas of a vacuum and of time without change. Hume does not, however, restrict his attention to these ideas; he also draws conclusions about space and time themselves. He argues that space and time are not infinitely divisible, that their smallest parts must be occupied, and that as a consequence there is no vacuum or interval of time without change. His treatments of matters beyond the scope of the sections title have received harsh criticism. His conclusions have seemed contrary to mathematics and physics. His method of arguing - applying features of our mere ideas of space and time to space and time themselves - has seemed philosophically inept. The apparent success of these criticisms has led to widespread neglect of this part of Humes work. The neglect is unfortunate. In Of the ideas of space and time Hume gives important characterizations of the skeptical approach that will be developed in the rest of the Treatise. When that approach is better understood, the force of Hume’s arguments concerning space and time can be appreciated, and the influential criticisms of them can be seen to miss the mark.


The Philosophical Review | 1993

The Cambridge companion to Hume

David Fate Norton; Jacqueline Taylor


Archive | 1993

Hume on religion

J. C. A. Gaskin; David Fate Norton; Jacqueline Taylor


Archive | 1993

The structure of Hume's political theory

Knud Haakonssen; David Fate Norton; Jacqueline Taylor


Archive | 1993

Hume's moral psychology

Terence Penelhum; David Fate Norton; Jacqueline Taylor


Hume Studies | 1998

Justice and the foundations of social morality in Hume's Treatise

Jacqueline Taylor

Collaboration


Dive into the Jacqueline Taylor's collaboration.

Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

John Biro

University of Florida

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Peter Jones

Sandia National Laboratories

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Knud Haakonssen

Australian National University

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Researchain Logo
Decentralizing Knowledge