Network


Latest external collaboration on country level. Dive into details by clicking on the dots.

Hotspot


Dive into the research topics where Jeffrey Alan Fletcher is active.

Publication


Featured researches published by Jeffrey Alan Fletcher.


Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences | 2009

A simple and general explanation for the evolution of altruism

Jeffrey Alan Fletcher; Michael Doebeli

We present a simple framework that highlights the most fundamental requirement for the evolution of altruism: assortment between individuals carrying the cooperative genotype and the helping behaviours of others with which these individuals interact. We partition the fitness effects on individuals into those due to self and those due to the ‘interaction environment’, and show that it is the latter that is most fundamental to understanding the evolution of altruism. We illustrate that while kinship or genetic similarity among those interacting may generate a favourable structure of interaction environments, it is not a fundamental requirement for the evolution of altruism, and even suicidal aid can theoretically evolve without help ever being exchanged among genetically similar individuals. Using our simple framework, we also clarify a common confusion made in the literature between alternative fitness accounting methods (which may equally apply to the same biological circumstances) and unique causal mechanisms for creating the assortment necessary for altruism to be favoured by natural selection.


The American Naturalist | 2006

Unifying the theories of inclusive fitness and reciprocal altruism.

Jeffrey Alan Fletcher; Martin Zwick

Inclusive fitness and reciprocal altruism are widely thought to be distinct explanations for how altruism evolves. Here we show that they rely on the same underlying mechanism. We demonstrate this commonality by applying Hamilton’s rule, normally associated with inclusive fitness, to two simple models of reciprocal altruism: one, an iterated prisoner’s dilemma model with conditional behavior; the other, a mutualistic symbiosis model where two interacting species differ in conditional behaviors, fitness benefits, and costs. We employ Queller’s generalization of Hamilton’s rule because the traditional version of this rule does not apply when genotype and phenotype frequencies differ or when fitness effects are nonadditive, both of which are true in classic models of reciprocal altruism. Queller’s equation is more general in that it applies to all situations covered by earlier versions of Hamilton’s rule but also handles nonadditivity, conditional behavior, and lack of genetic similarity between altruists and recipients. Our results suggest changes to standard interpretations of Hamilton’s rule that focus on kinship and indirect fitness. Despite being more than 20 years old, Queller’s generalization of Hamilton’s rule is not sufficiently appreciated, especially its implications for the unification of the theories of inclusive fitness and reciprocal altruism.


Evolution | 2013

TOWARDS A GENERAL THEORY OF GROUP SELECTION

Burton Simon; Jeffrey Alan Fletcher; Michael Doebeli

The longstanding debate about the importance of group (multilevel) selection suffers from a lack of formal models that describe explicit selection events at multiple levels. Here, we describe a general class of models for two‐level evolutionary processes which include birth and death events at both levels. The models incorporate the state‐dependent rates at which these events occur. The models come in two closely related forms: (1) a continuous‐time Markov chain, and (2) a partial differential equation (PDE) derived from (1) by taking a limit. We argue that the mathematical structure of this PDE is the same for all models of two‐level population processes, regardless of the kinds of events featured in the model. The mathematical structure of the PDE allows for a simple and unambiguous way to distinguish between individual‐ and group‐level events in any two‐level population model. This distinction, in turn, suggests a new and intuitively appealing way to define group selection in terms of the effects of group‐level events. We illustrate our theory of group selection by applying it to models of the evolution of cooperation and the evolution of simple multicellular organisms, and then demonstrate that this kind of group selection is not mathematically equivalent to individual‐level (kin) selection.


Journal of Evolutionary Biology | 2006

How Altruism Evolves: Assortment and Synergy

Jeffrey Alan Fletcher; Michael Doebeli

If one defines altruism strictly at the population level such that carriers of the altruistic genotype are required to experience, on average, a net fitness cost relative to average population members, then altruism can never evolve. This is simply because a genetically encoded trait can only increase in a population (relative to alternative traits) if the mean fitness of individuals carrying this genotype is higher than the population average fitness. This is true whether the genotype of interest encodes a self-serving behaviour such as enhanced predator avoidance, or an altruistic behaviour in which the actor enhances the fitness of those it interacts with more than its own. The paradox in the evolution of altruism is that carriers that are, on average, at a local disadvantage (i.e. compared to those they interact with) can still have higher fitness than the population average and hence can increase overall. The most fundamental explanation for how altruism (defined by local interactions) increases in a population requires that there be assortment in the population such that the benefit from others falls sufficiently often to carriers (and at the same time nonaltruists are stuck interacting more with each other). Nonadditivity if present can play a similar role: when collective cooperation yields synergistic benefits (positive nonadditivity) altruistic behaviour can evolve even in the absence of positive assortment, and when there are diminishing returns for cooperation (negative nonadditivity) the evolution of altruism is hindered (Queller, 1985; Hauert et al., 2006). In their target article Lehmann & Keller (2006) use a form of Hamilton’s rule (1964, 1975) to classify different mechanisms by which helping behaviours can evolve. However, the version they develop tends to obscure the fundamental roles that assortment and nonadditivity play. Their framework also confuses local and population-wide definitions of altruism in making distinctions between nonrelatives and relatives, and what they label as mere ‘cooperation’ vs. true ‘altruism’. We argue that a previous generalization of Hamilton’s rule developed by Queller (1985) makes clear the roles played by assortment and nonadditivity and therefore serves as a better starting point for classifying various proposed models and mechanism of how altruistic traits can evolve.


Nature | 2010

Multilevel and Kin Selection in a Connected World

Michael J. Wade; David Sloan Wilson; Charles J. Goodnight; Doug Taylor; Yaneer Bar-Yam; Marcus A. M. de Aguiar; Blake C. Stacey; Justin Werfel; Guy A. Hoelzer; Edmund D. Brodie; Peter D. Fields; Felix Breden; Timothy A. Linksvayer; Jeffrey Alan Fletcher; Peter J. Richerson; James D. Bever; J. David Van Dyken; Peter C. Zee

Arising from: G. Wild, A. Gardner & S. A. West 459, 983–986 (2009)10.1038/nature08071; Wild, Gardner & West replyWild et al. argue that the evolution of reduced virulence can be understood from the perspective of inclusive fitness, obviating the need to evoke group selection as a contributing causal factor. Although they acknowledge the mathematical equivalence of the inclusive fitness and multilevel selection approaches, they conclude that reduced virulence can be viewed entirely as an individual-level adaptation by the parasite. Here we show that their model is a well-known special case of the more general theory of multilevel selection, and that the cause of reduced virulence resides in the opposition of two processes: within-group and among-group selection. This distinction is important in light of the current controversy among evolutionary biologists in which some continue to affirm that natural selection centres only and always at the level of the individual organism or gene, despite mathematical demonstrations that evolutionary dynamics must be described by selection at various levels in the hierarchy of biological organization.


The American Naturalist | 2004

The Kin Composition of Social Groups: Trading Group Size for Degree of Altruism

Leticia Avilés; Jeffrey Alan Fletcher; Asher D. Cutter

Why some social systems form groups composed of kin, while others do not, has gone largely untreated in the literature. Using an individual‐based simulation model, we explore the demographic consequences of making kinship a criterion in group formation. We find that systems where social groups consist of one‐generation breeding associations may face a serious trade‐off between degree of altruism and group size that is largely mediated by their kin composition. On the one hand, restricting groups to close kin allows the evolution of highly altruistic behaviors but may limit group size to suboptimal levels, the more severely so the smaller the intrinsic fecundity of the species and the stricter the kin admission rule. Group size requirements, on the other hand, can be met by admitting nonkin into groups, but not without limiting the degree of altruism that can evolve. As a solution to this conundrum, we show that if helping roles within groups are assigned through a lottery rather than being genetically determined, maximum degrees of altruism can evolve in groups of nonrelatives of any size. Such a “lottery” mechanism may explain reproductive and helping patterns in organisms as varied as the cellular slime molds, pleometrotic ants, and Galapagos hawks.


Journal of Theoretical Biology | 2012

Hamilton's Rule in Multi-level Selection Models

Burton Simon; Jeffrey Alan Fletcher; Michael Doebeli

Hamiltons rule is regarded as a useful tool in the understanding of social evolution, but it relies on restrictive, overly simple assumptions. Here we model more realistic situations, in which the traditional Hamiltons rule generally fails to predict the direction of selection. We offer modifications that allow accurate predictions, but also show that these Hamiltons rule type inequalities do not predict long-term outcomes. To illustrate these issues we propose a two-level selection model for the evolution of cooperation. The model describes the dynamics of a population of groups of cooperators and defectors of various sizes and compositions and contains birth-death processes at both the individual level and the group level. We derive Hamilton-like inequalities that accurately predict short-term evolutionary change, but do not reliably predict long-term evolutionary dynamics. Over evolutionary time, cooperators and defectors can repeatedly change roles as the favored type, because the amount of assortment between cooperators changes in complicated ways due to both individual-level and group-level processes. The equation that governs the dynamics of cooperator/defector assortment is a certain partial differential equation, which can be solved numerically, but whose behaviour cannot be predicted by Hamiltons rules, because Hamiltons rules only contain first-derivative information. In addition, Hamiltons rules are sensitive to demographic fitness effects such as local crowding, and hence models that assume constant group sizes are not equivalent to models like ours that relax that assumption. In the long-run, the group distribution typically reaches an equilibrium, in which case Hamiltons rules necessarily become equalities.


PLOS ONE | 2012

Spatio-temporal differentiation and sociality in spiders.

Jessica Purcell; João Vasconcellos-Neto; Marcelo O. Gonzaga; Jeffrey Alan Fletcher; Leticia Avilés

Species that differ in their social system, and thus in traits such as group size and dispersal timing, may differ in their use of resources along spatial, temporal, or dietary dimensions. The role of sociality in creating differences in habitat use is best explored by studying closely related species or socially polymorphic species that differ in their social system, but share a common environment. Here we investigate whether five sympatric Anelosimus spider species that range from nearly solitary to highly social differ in their use of space and in their phenology as a function of their social system. By studying these species in Serra do Japi, Brazil, we find that the more social species, which form larger, longer–lived colonies, tend to live inside the forest, where sturdier, longer lasting vegetation is likely to offer better support for their nests. The less social species, which form single-family groups, in contrast, tend to occur on the forest edge where the vegetation is less robust. Within these two microhabitats, species with longer-lived colonies tend to occupy the potentially more stable positions closer to the core of the plants, while those with smaller and shorter-lived colonies build their nests towards the branch tips. The species further separate in their use of common habitat due to differences in the timing of their reproductive season. These patterns of habitat use suggest that the degree of sociality can enable otherwise similar species to differ from one another in ways that may facilitate their co-occurrence in a shared environment, a possibility that deserves further consideration.


Adaptive Behavior | 1996

Dependence of adaptability on environmental structure in a simple evolutionary model

Jeffrey Alan Fletcher; Mark A. Bedau; Martin Zwick

This article concerns the relationship between the detectable and useful structure in an environment and the degree to which a population can adapt to that environment. We explore the hypothesis that adaptability will depend unimodally on environmental variety, and we measure this component of environmental structure using the information-theoretical uncertainty (Shannon entropy) of detectable environmental conditions. We define adaptability as the degree to which a certain kind of population successfully adapts to a certain kind of environment, and we measure adaptability by comparing a populations size to the size of a nonadapting, but otherwise comparable, population in the same environment. We study the relationship between adaptability and environmental structure in an evolving artificial population of sensorimotor agents that live, reproduce, and die in a variety of environments. We find that adaptability does not show a unimodal dependence on environmental variety alone, although there is justification for preserving our unimodal hypothesis if we consider other aspects of environmental structure. In particular, adaptability depends not just on how much structural information is detectable in the environment but also on the extent to which this information is unambiguous and valuable (i.e., whether the information accurately signals a difference that makes a difference). How best to measure and integrate these other components of environmental structure remains unresolved.


Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences | 2010

Assortment is a more fundamental explanation for the evolution of altruism than inclusive fitness or multilevel selection: reply to Bijma and Aanen

Jeffrey Alan Fletcher; Michael Doebeli

Broadly speaking, altruistic traits can be thought of in two categories: those where the benefits of a helpful behaviour go only to others (excluding the actor), and those where these benefits go towards some common good, a portion of which feed back to the actor. In both cases the actor alone bears

Collaboration


Dive into the Jeffrey Alan Fletcher's collaboration.

Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Martin Zwick

Portland State University

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Michael Doebeli

University of British Columbia

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Burton Simon

University of Colorado Denver

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Leticia Avilés

University of British Columbia

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Marcelo O. Gonzaga

State University of Campinas

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Researchain Logo
Decentralizing Knowledge