Michael Detlefsen
University of Notre Dame
Network
Latest external collaboration on country level. Dive into details by clicking on the dots.
Publication
Featured researches published by Michael Detlefsen.
The Journal of Philosophy | 1991
Mark Steiner; Michael Detlefsen
I: The Philosophical Fundamentals of Hilberts Program.- II: A Closer Look at the Problems.- III: The Godelian Challenge.- IV: The Stability Problem.- V: The Convergence Problem and the Problem of Strict Instrumentalism.- Appendix: Hilberts Program and the First Theorem.- References.
Synthese | 1992
Michael Detlefsen
Poincaré was a persistent critic of logicism. Unlike most critics of logicism, however, he did not focus his attention on the basic laws of the logicists or the question of their genuinely logical status. Instead, he directed his remarks against the place accorded to logical inference in the logicists conception of mathematical proof. Following Leibniz, traditional logicist dogma (and this is explicit in Frege) has held that reasoning or inference is everywhere the same — that there are no principles of inference specific to a given local topic. Poincaré, a Kantian, disagreed with this. Indeed, he believed that the use of non-logical reasoning was essential to genuinely mathematical reasoning (proof). In this essay, I try to isolate and clarify this idea and to describe the mathematical epistemology which underlies it. Central to this epistemology (which is basically Kantian in orientation, and closely similar to that advocated by Brouwer) is a principle of epistemic conservation which says that knowledge of a given type cannot be extended by means of an inference unless that inference itself constitutes knowledge belonging to the given type.
Journal of Philosophical Logic | 1979
Michael Detlefsen
SummaryIn this paper I have considered various attempts to attribute significance to G2.25 Two of these attempts (Beth-Cohen and the position maintaining that G2 shows the failure of Hilberts Program), I have argued, are literally false. Two others (BCR and Resniks Interpretation), I have argued, are groundless.
Archive for History of Exact Sciences | 1976
Michael Detlefsen; Douglas K. Erlandson; J. Clark Heston; Charles M. Young
It is widely held that c o m p u t a t i o n with R o m a n numera l s is difficult if no t i m p o s s i b l e ) By presen t ing s imple p rocedure s for add ing and mul t ip ly ing with R o m a n numerals , we show tha t this c o m m o n idea is mis taken . We also suggest that its accep tance arises f rom the m i s t a k e n bel ief tha t c o m p u t a t i o n s in different numera l systems will m i r ro r one ano the r , a belief which can be expla ined as depend ing upon a confus ion of numera l s with numbers .
Minds and Machines | 2002
Michael Detlefsen
We argue that Löbs Theorem implies a limitation on mechanism. Specifically, we argue, via an application of a generalized version of Löbs Theorem, that any particular device known by an observer to be mechanical cannot be used as an epistemic authority (of a particular type) by that observer: either the belief-set of such an authority is not mechanizable or, if it is, there is no identifiable formal system of which the observer can know (or truly believe) it to be the theorem-set. This gives, we believe, an important and hitherto unnoticed connection between mechanism and the use of authorities by human-like epistemic agents.
Archive | 2015
Michael Detlefsen
In June of 1936 Gentzen gave a lecture at Heinrich Scholz’ seminar in Munster. The title of the lecture was “Der Unendlichkeitsbegriff in der Mathematik.”1
Archive | 2015
Michael Detlefsen
The central concerns of this chapter are to (i) identify the chief motives which led Hilbert to develop his “direct” approach to the consistency problem for arithmetic and to (ii) expose certain relationships between these motives. Of particular concern will be the question of the role played by conceptual freedom (i.e. freedom in use of concepts) in this development. If I am right, Hilbert was motivated by an ideal of freedom, though it was only one of a number of factors that shaped his proof theory.
Archive | 1986
Michael Detlefsen
The primary goal of this chapter is to give a careful statement of what, for want of a more descriptive title, we refer to as the Standard Argument against Hilbert’s Program (or the SA, for short). This argument, as the title of the chapter suggests, is that which is derived from Godel’s Second Incompleteness Theorem (or G2, as we shall refer to it from here on out).
Archive | 1986
Michael Detlefsen
The main issue of this chapter concerns how the epistemic benefits of an ideal system may come to be distributed over it. In particular, we are interested in whether they are evenly or unevenly distributed over it; where to say that the epistemic benefits of T are evenly distributed over it is to say that there is no isolable subsystem of T containing all or nearly all of its humanly useful ideal proofs. When the epistemic benefits of a system can be compressed into one of its parts, we say that the system is “localizable”.
Archive | 1986
Michael Detlefsen
Presumably, if the Godelian is to find a solution to the Stability Problem for a given system T (T being an ideal system whose soundness is in question, and therefore a system whose syntax is to be represented or “arithmetized”) he must locate a set C of conditions on formulae of T (T now being treated also as the system in which the syntax of T is to be represented) such that (1) every formula of T that can reasonably be said to express the consistency of T satisfies the conditions in C, and (2) no formula of T that satisfies C can be proven in T provided that T is consistent. This being so, the Godelian’s success in dealing with the Stability Problem will evidently depend crucially upon his ability to defend the reasonableness of his choice of C.