Network


Latest external collaboration on country level. Dive into details by clicking on the dots.

Hotspot


Dive into the research topics where Roman Frigg is active.

Publication


Featured researches published by Roman Frigg.


Synthese | 2010

Models and Fiction

Roman Frigg

Most scientific models are not physical objects, and this raises important questions. What sort of entity are models, what is truth in a model, and how do we learn about models? In this paper I argue that models share important aspects in common with literary fiction, and that therefore theories of fiction can be brought to bear on these questions. In particular, I argue that the pretence theory as developed by Walton (1990, Mimesis as make-believe: on the foundations of the representational arts. Harvard University Press, Cambridge/MA) has the resources to answer these questions. I introduce this account, outline the answers that it offers, and develop a general picture of scientific modelling based on it.


Synthese | 2009

The philosophy of simulation: hot new issues or same old stew?

Roman Frigg; Julian Reiss

Computer simulations are an exciting tool that plays important roles in many scientific disciplines. This has attracted the attention of a number of philosophers of science. The main tenor in this literature is that computer simulations not only constitute interesting and powerful new science, but that they also raise a host of new philosophical issues. The protagonists in this debate claim no less than that simulations call into question our philosophical understanding of scientific ontology, the epistemology and semantics of models and theories, and the relation between experimentation and theorising, and submit that simulations demand a fundamentally new philosophy of science in many respects. The aim of this paper is to critically evaluate these claims. Our conclusion will be sober. We argue that these claims are overblown and that simulations, far from demanding a new metaphysics, epistemology, semantics and methodology, raise few if any new philosophical problems. The philosophical problems that do come up in connection with simulations are not specific to simulations and most of them are variants of problems that have been discussed in other contexts before.


Studies in History and Philosophy of Science | 2003

Self-organised criticality—what it is and what it isn’t

Roman Frigg

The last decade and a half has seen an ardent development of self-organised criticality (SOC), a new approach to complex systems, which has become important in many domains of natural as well as social science, such as geology, biology, astronomy, and economics, to mention just a few. This has led many to adopt a generalist stance towards SOC, which is now repeatedly claimed to be a universal theory of complex behaviour. The aim of this paper is twofold. First, I provide a brief and non-technical introduction to SOC. Second, I critically discuss the various bold claims that have been made in connection with it. Throughout, I will adopt a rather sober attitude and argue that some people have been too readily carried away by fancy contentions. My overall conclusion will be that none of these bold claims can be maintained. Nevertheless, stripped of exaggerated expectations and daring assertions, many SOC models are interesting vehicles for promising scientific research.


Archive | 2010

Fiction and Scientific Representation

Roman Frigg

Most scientific models are not physical objects. But what sort of objects are they? What is truth in a model, and how do we learn about models? In this first part of this chapter I develop an answer to these questions based on the so-called pretense theory of literary fiction. In the second part I draw on the analogy between maps and models to develop an account of scientific representation and discuss in detail the Newtonian model of the planetary system to illustrate how the account works.


The present situation in the philosophy of science, 2010, ISBN 978-90-481-9114-7, págs. 351-371 | 2010

Determinism and Chance from a Humean Perspective

Roman Frigg; Carl Hoefer

On the face of it ‘deterministic chance’ is an oxymoron: either a process is chancy or deterministic, but not both. Nevertheless, the world is rife with processes that seem to be exactly that: chancy and deterministic at once. Simple gambling devices like coins and dice are cases in point.2 On the one hand they are governed by deterministic laws – the laws of classical mechanics – and hence given the initial condition of, say, a coin it is determined whether it will land heads or tails when tossed.3 On the other hand, we commonly assign probabilities to the different outcomes of a coin toss, and doing so has proven successful in guiding our actions. The same dilemma also emerges in less mundane contexts. Classical statistical mechanics assigns probabilities to the occurrence of certain events – for instance to the spreading of a gas that is originally confined to the left half of a container – but at the same time assumes that the relevant systems are deterministic. How can this apparent conflict be resolved?


Philosophy of Science | 2013

The Myopia of Imperfect Climate Models: The Case of UKCP09

Roman Frigg; Leonard A. Smith; David A. Stainforth

The United Kingdom Climate Impacts Program’s UKCP09 project makes high-resolution forecasts of climate during the twenty-first century using state of the art global climate models. The aim of this article is to introduce and analyze the methodology used and then urge some caution. Given the acknowledged systematic errors in all current climate models, treating model outputs as decision-relevant probabilistic forecasts can be seriously misleading. This casts doubt on our ability, today, to make trustworthy, high-resolution predictions out to the end of this century.


Philosophy of Science | 2009

Typicality and the Approach to Equilibrium in Boltzmannian Statistical Mechanics

Roman Frigg

An important contemporary version of Boltzmannian statistical mechanics explains the approach to equilibrium in terms of typicality. The problem with this approach is that it comes in different versions, which are, however, not recognized as such and not clearly distinguished. This article identifies three different versions of typicality‐based explanations of thermodynamic‐like behavior and evaluates their respective successes. The conclusion is that the first two are unsuccessful because they fail to take the systems dynamics into account. The third, however, is promising. I give a precise formulation of the proposal and present an argument in support of its central contention.


Archive | 2011

Why Typicality Does Not Explain the Approach to Equilibrium

Roman Frigg

Why do systems prepared in a non-equilibrium state approach, and eventually reach, equilibrium? An important contemporary version of the Boltzmannian approach to statistical mechanics answers this question by an appeal to the notion of typicality. The problem with this approach is that it comes in different versions, which are, however, not recognised as such, much less clearly distinguished, and we often find different arguments pursued side by side. The aim of this paper is to disentangle different versions of typicality-based explanations of thermodynamic behaviour and evaluate their respective success. My conclusion will be that the boldest version fails for technical reasons, while more prudent versions leave unanswered essential questions.


Philosophy of Science | 2014

Laplace’s Demon and the Adventures of His Apprentices

Roman Frigg; Seamus Bradley; Hailiang Du; Leonard A. Smith

The sensitive dependence on initial conditions (SDIC) associated with nonlinear models imposes limitations on the models’ predictive power. We draw attention to an additional limitation than has been underappreciated, namely, structural model error (SME). A model has SME if the model dynamics differ from the dynamics in the target system. If a nonlinear model has only the slightest SME, then its ability to generate decision-relevant predictions is compromised. Given a perfect model, we can take the effects of SDIC into account by substituting probabilistic predictions for point predictions. This route is foreclosed in the case of SME, which puts us in a worse epistemic situation than SDIC.


Philosophy of Science | 2008

Chance in Boltzmannian statistical mechanics

Roman Frigg

In two recent papers Barry Loewer (2001, 2004) has suggested to interpret probabilities in statistical mechanics as chances in David Lewis’s (1994) sense. I first give a precise formulation of this proposal, then raise two fundamental objections, and finally conclude that these can be overcome only at the price of interpreting these probabilities epistemically.

Collaboration


Dive into the Roman Frigg's collaboration.

Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Charlotte Werndl

London School of Economics and Political Science

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Leonard A. Smith

London School of Economics and Political Science

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

James Nguyen

University of Notre Dame

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Carl Hoefer

Autonomous University of Barcelona

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

David A. Stainforth

London School of Economics and Political Science

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Erica Thompson

London School of Economics and Political Science

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Hailiang Du

London School of Economics and Political Science

View shared research outputs
Researchain Logo
Decentralizing Knowledge