Network


Latest external collaboration on country level. Dive into details by clicking on the dots.

Hotspot


Dive into the research topics where S. Barry Cooper is active.

Publication


Featured researches published by S. Barry Cooper.


Annals of Pure and Applied Logic | 1991

The d.r.e. degrees are not dense

S. Barry Cooper; Leo Harrington; Alistair H. Lachlan; Steffen Lempp; Robert I. Soare

Abstract By constructing a maximal incomplete d.r.e. degree, the nondensity of the partial order of the d.r.e. degrees is established. An easy modification yields the nondensity of the n -r.e. degrees ( n ⩾2) and of the ω-r.e. degrees.


Journal of Symbolic Logic | 1985

On minimal pairs of enumeration degrees

Kevin McEvoy; S. Barry Cooper

For sets of natural numbers A and B, A is enumeration reducible to B if there is some effective algorithm which when given any enumeration of B will produce an enumeration of A . Gutteridge [5] has shown that in the upper semilattice of the enumeration degrees there are no minimal degrees (see Cooper [3]), and in this paper we study those pairs of degrees with gib 0 . Case [1] constructed a minimal pair. This minimal pair construction can be relativised to any gib, and following a suggestion of Jockusch we can also fix one of the degrees and still construct the pair. These methods yield an easier proof of Cases exact pair theorem for countable ideals. 0″ is an upper bound for the minimal pair constructed in §1, and in §2 we improve this bound to any Σ 2 -high Δ 2 degree. In contrast to this we show that every low degree c bounds a degree a which is not in any minimal pair bounded by c . The structure of the co-r.e. e-degrees is isomorphic to that of the r.e. Turing degrees, and Gutteridge has constructed co-r.e. degrees which form a minimal pair in the e-degrees. In §3 we show that if a, b is any minimal pair of co-r.e. degrees such that a is low then a, b is a minimal pair in the e-degrees (and so Gutteridges result follows). As a corollary of this we can embed any countable distributive lattice and the two nondistributive five-element lattices in the e-degrees below 0′. However the lowness assumption is necessary, as we also prove that there is a minimal pair of (high) r.e. degrees which is not a minimal pair in the e-degrees (under the isomorphism). In §4 we present more concise proofs of some unpublished work of Lagemann on bounding incomparable pairs and embedding partial orderings. As usual, { W i } i ∈ ω is the standard listing of the recursively enumerable sets, D u is the finite set with canonical index u and {‹ m, n ›} m, n ∈ ω is a recursive, one-to-one coding of the pairs of numbers onto the numbers. Capital italic letters will be variables over sets of natural numbers, and lower case boldface letters from the beginning of the alphabet will vary over degrees.


Archive | 2003

Incomputability in Nature

S. Barry Cooper; Piergiorgio Odifreddi

To what extent is incomputability relevant to the material Universe? We look at ways in which this question might be answered, and the extent to which the theory of computability, which grew out of the work of Godel, Church, Kleene and Turing, can contribute to a clear resolution of the current confusion. It is hoped that the presentation will be accessible to the non-specialist reader.


Israel Journal of Mathematics | 1989

Weak density and cupping in the d-r.e. degrees

S. Barry Cooper; Steffen Lempp; Philip Watson

Consider the Turing degrees of differences of recursively enumerable sets (the d-r.e. degrees). We show that there is a properly d-r.e. degree (a d-r.e. degree that is not r.e.) between any two comparable r.e. degrees, and that given a high r.e. degreeh, every nonrecursive d-r.e. degree ≦h cups toh by a low d-r.e. degree.


Annals of Pure and Applied Logic | 1996

Cupping and noncupping in the enumeration degrees of ∑20 sets

S. Barry Cooper; Andrea Sorbi; Xiaoding Yi

Abstract We prove the following three theorems on the enumeration degrees of ∑ 2 0 sets. Theorem A: There exists a nonzero noncuppable ∑ 2 0 enumeration degree. Theorem B: Every nonzero Δ 2 0 enumeration degree is cuppable to 0′ e by an incomplete total enumeration degree. Theorem C: There exists a nonzero low Δ 2 0 enumeration degree with the anticupping property .


Archive | 2012

How the World Computes

S. Barry Cooper; Anuj Dawar; Benedikt Löwe

Partial Cylindrical Algebraic Decomposition I: The Lifting Phase . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 560 Grant Olney Passmore and Paul B. Jackson Multi-valued Functions in Computability Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 571 Arno Pauly Relative Randomness for Martin-Löf Random Sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 581 NingNing Peng, Kojiro Higuchi, Takeshi Yamazaki, and Kazuyuki Tanaka Table ofThe idea that the Universe is a program in a giant quantum computer is both fascinating and suffers from various problems. Nonetheless, it can provide a unified picture of physics and this can be very useful for the problem of Quantum Gravity where such a unification is necessary. In previous work we proposed Quantum Graphity, a simple way to model a dynamical spacetime as a quantum computation. In this paper, we give an easily readable introduction to the idea of the universe as a quantum computation, the problem of quantum gravity, and the graphity models.


The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic | 2002

First Steps into Metapredicativity in Explicit Mathematics

Thomas Strahm; S. Barry Cooper; J. K. Truss

Metapredicativity is a new general term in proof theory which describes the analysis and study of formal systems whose proof-theoretic strength is beyond the Feferman-Schutte ordinal Γ0 but which are nevertheless amenable to purely predicative methods. Typical examples of formal systems which are apt for scaling the initial part of metapredicativity are the transfinitely iterated fixed point theories IDα whose detailed proof-theoretic analysis is given by Jager, Kahle, Setzer and Strahm in [18]. In this paper we assume familiarity with [18]. For natural extensions of Friedman’s ATR that can be measured against transfinitely iterated fixed point theories the reader is referred to Jager and Strahm [20]. In the mid seventies, Feferman [3, 4] introduced systems of explicit mathematics in order to provide an alternative foundation of constructive mathematics. More precisely, it was the origin of Feferman’s program to give a logical account of Bishop-style constructive mathematics. Right from the beginning, systems of explicit mathematics turned out to be of general interest for proof theory, mainly in connection with the proof-theoretic analysis of subsystems of first and second order arithmetic and set theory, cf. e.g. Jager [15] and Jager and Pohlers [19]. More recently, systems of explicit mathematics have been used to develop a general logical framework for functional programming and type theory, where it is possible to derive correctness and termination properties of functional programs. Important references in this connection are Feferman [6, 7, 9] and Jager [17]. Universes are a frequently studied concept in constructive mathematics at least since the work of Martin-Lof, cf. e.g. Martin-Lof [23] or Palmgren [27] for


Communications of The ACM | 2012

Turing's Titanic machine?

S. Barry Cooper

Embodied and disembodied computing at the Turing Centenary.


Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society | 1992

A splitting theorem for the n-r.e. degrees

S. Barry Cooper

We prove a splitting theorem for the n-r.e. degrees, of which the Sacks Splitting Theorem [9] for the r.e. (=1-r.e.) degrees is a special case. For background terminology and notation see [4] and [11]


Mathematical Logic Quarterly | 2000

There is No Low Maximal D.C.E. Degree

M. M. Arslanov; S. Barry Cooper; Angsheng Li

AbstractWe show that for any computably enumerable (c.e.) degree a andany low n–c.e. degree l (n ≥ 1), if l< a, then there are n–c.e. degreesa 0 ,a 1 such that l< a 0 ,a 1 < a and a 0 ∨a 1 = a. In particular, thereis no low maximal d.c.e. degree. 1 Introduction A set A is n-c.e. if there is a computable function f(x,s) such that for everyx f(x,0) = 0 , lim s f(x,s) = A(x), and |{s : f(x,s) 6= f(x,s+1)}| ≤ n.So, in particular, the 1-c.e. sets are precisely the c.e. sets. The 2-c.e. setsare also known as the d.c.e. sets as they are the differences of c.e. sets, i.e.the ones of the form B − C with both B and C c.e. Similarly the n-c.e.sets are those obtained by starting with c.e. sets and alternating the Booleanoperations of difference and union.A (Turing) degree is called n–c.e. if it contains an n–c.e. set. An(n + 1)–c.e. degree is a properly (n + 1)–c.e. degree if it contains no n–c.e. set. As for sets, a 1–c.e. degree is a c.e. degree, and a 2–c.e. de-gree is called a d.c.e. degree. Let D

Collaboration


Dive into the S. Barry Cooper's collaboration.

Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Angsheng Li

Chinese Academy of Sciences

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Steffen Lempp

University of Wisconsin-Madison

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Anuj Dawar

University of Cambridge

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Jin-Yi Cai

University of Wisconsin-Madison

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Manindra Agrawal

Indian Institute of Technology Kanpur

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

George Barmpalias

Chinese Academy of Sciences

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Researchain Logo
Decentralizing Knowledge