Network


Latest external collaboration on country level. Dive into details by clicking on the dots.

Hotspot


Dive into the research topics where Sean Dorrance Kelly is active.

Publication


Featured researches published by Sean Dorrance Kelly.


Ratio | 2002

Merleau-Ponty on the body

Sean Dorrance Kelly

The French philosopher Maurice Merleau–Ponty claims that there are two distinct ways in which we can understand the place of an object when we are visually apprehending it. The first involves an intentional relation to the object that is essentially cognitive or can serve as the input to cognitive processes; the second irreducibly involves a bodily set or preparation to deal with the object. Because of its essential bodily component, Merleau–Ponty calls this second kind of understanding ‘motor intentional’. In this paper I consider some phenomenological, conceptual, and cognitive neuro–scientific results that help to elucidate and defend the distinction between intentional and motor intentional activity. I go on to argue that motor intentional activity has a logical structure that is essentially distinct from that of the more canonical kinds of intentional states. In particular, the characteristic logical distinction between the content and the attitude of an intentional state does not carry over to the motor intentional case.


Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience | 2006

A Moment to Reflect upon Perceptual Synchrony

Mark A. Elliott; Zhuanghua Shi; Sean Dorrance Kelly

How does neuronal activity bring about the interpretation of visual space in terms of objects or complex perceptual events? If they group, simple visual features can bring about the integration of spikes from neurons responding to different features to within a few milliseconds. Considered as a potential solution to the binding problem, it is suggested that neuronal synchronization is the glue for binding together different features of the same object. This idea receives some support from correlated- and periodic-stimulus motion paradigms, both of which suggest that the segregation of a figure from ground is a direct result of the temporal correlation of visual signals. One could say that perception of a highly correlated visual structure permits space to be bound in time. However, on closer analysis, the concept of perceptual synchrony is insufficient to explain the conditions under which events will be seen as simultaneous. Instead, the grouping effects ascribed to perceptual synchrony are better explained in terms of the intervals of time over which stimulus events integrate and seem to occur simultaneously. This point is supported by the equivalence of some of these measures with well-established estimates of the perceptual moment. However, it is time in extension and not the instantaneous that may best describe how seemingly simultaneous features group. This means that studies of perceptual synchrony are insufficient to address the binding problem.


Philosophical Psychology | 2000

Phenomenology, dynamical neural networks and brain function

Donald S. Borrett; Sean Dorrance Kelly; Hon C. Kwan

Current cognitive science models of perception and action assume that the objects that we move toward and perceive are represented as determinate in our experience of them. A proper phenomenology of perception and action, however, shows that we experience objects indeterminately when we are perceiving them or moving toward them. This indeterminacy, as it relates to simple movement and perception, is captured in the proposed phenomenologically based recurrent network models of brain function. These models provide a possible foundation from which predicative structures may arise as an emergent phenomenon without the positing of a representing subject. These models go some way in addressing the dual constraints of phenomenological accuracy and neurophysiological plausibility that ought to guide all projects devoted to discovering the physical basis of human experience.


Philosophical Psychology | 2000

Bridging embodied cognition and brain function: The role of phenomenology

Donald S. Borrett; Sean Dorrance Kelly; Hon C. Kwan

Both cognitive science and phenomenology accept the primacy of the organism-environment system and recognize that cognition should be understood in terms of an embodied agent situated in its environment. How embodiment is seen to shape our world, however, is fundamentally different in these two disciplines. Embodiment, as understood in cognitive science, reduces to a discussion of the consequences of having a body like ours interacting with our environment and the relationship is one of contingent causality. Embodiment, as understood phenomenologically, represents the condition of intelligibility of certain terms in our experience and, as such, refers to one aspect of that background which presupposes our understanding of the world. The goals and approach to modeling an embodied agent in its environment are also fundamentally different dependent on which relationship is addressed. These differences are highlighted and are used to support our phenomenologically based approach to organism-environment interaction and its relationship to brain function.


Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines | 2011

Saving the Sacred from the Axial Revolution

Hubert L. Dreyfus; Sean Dorrance Kelly

Abstract Prominent defenders of the Enlightenment, like Jürgen Habermas, are beginning to recognize that the characterization of human beings in entirely rational and secular terms leaves out something important. Religion, they admit, plays an important role in human existence. But the return to a traditional monotheistic religion seems sociologically difficult after the death of God. We argue that Homeric polytheism retains a phenomenologically rich account of the sacred, and a similarly rich understanding of human existence in its midst. By opening ourselves up to the moods of wonder and gratitude at the root of Homers sense of the sacred, we can re-appropriate a polytheistic understanding of the sacred that allows us to recover and revive the intensity and meaningfulness that Homers polytheists enjoyed.


Archive | 2009

Can one act for a reason without acting intentionally

Joshua Knobe; Sean Dorrance Kelly

Since the important work of Elizabeth Anscombe (1957), philosophers have been almost unanimous in accepting the claim that every behavior performed for a reason is performed intentionally. We develop and discuss here an apparent counterexample to this claim—a case in which people are inclined to say that an agent has performed a behavior for a reason, but are not inclined to say that he has performed that behavior intentionally.


The Philosophical Review | 2001

Demonstrative Concepts and Experience

Sean Dorrance Kelly


Archive | 2011

All Things Shining: Reading the Western Classics to Find Meaning in a Secular Age

Hubert L. Dreyfus; Sean Dorrance Kelly


Philosophy and Phenomenological Research | 2001

The Non‐conceptual Content of Perceptual Experience: Situation Dependence and Fineness of Grain

Sean Dorrance Kelly


Phenomenology and The Cognitive Sciences | 2007

Heterophenomenology: Heavy-handed sleight-of-hand

Hubert L. Dreyfus; Sean Dorrance Kelly

Collaboration


Dive into the Sean Dorrance Kelly's collaboration.

Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Donald S. Borrett

Toronto East General Hospital

View shared research outputs
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar
Top Co-Authors

Avatar

Mark A. Elliott

National University of Ireland

View shared research outputs
Researchain Logo
Decentralizing Knowledge