Network


Latest external collaboration on country level. Dive into details by clicking on the dots.

Hotspot


Dive into the research topics where Sigurd Burckhardt is active.

Publication


Featured researches published by Sigurd Burckhardt.


American Political Science Review | 1960

English Bards and APSR Reviewers

Sigurd Burckhardt

Recently the Review has extended its hospitality to studies which are not, technically, within the discipline it serves. A new school of Shakespeare criticism may be in the making; and since everyone deplores departmentalization, one should like to welcome, without misgivings, APSR publication of two Shakespeare interpretations. But I, for one, do have misgivings. It may be that the views of the authors are useful and needful for political theory; of that I am no judge. But I am sure that to present these views as Shakespeares can serve neither political theory nor Shakespeare criticism. The study of Shakespeare can profit from a knowledge of the history of political theory; and we on the belletristic side of the quad like to think that we are not the sole beneficiaries of the exchange. But the two articles in question go beyond this simple form of barter; they are interpretations of dramatic poetry. They do not accept and retail what Shakespeare criticism has concluded about the poets political philosophy; they are ambitious attempts to discover this philosophy by taking a direct and novel look at some Shakespearean texts. That is a praiseworthy ambition; but it demands something the authors do not have nor even know they lack: an adequate concept of the specificity of literature as a mode of discourse different from other modes. They have a worthy aim: to give a great poet a voice in the great concerns of practical life. But they have not yet learned to distinguish between the poets voice and their own—so that, though I greet the aim, I must withhold the applause.


ELH | 1956

The Poet as Fool and Priest

Sigurd Burckhardt

We know of Goethe that he was prompted to resume work on his tragedy of the poet -Torquato Tasso-while he was modelling a foot in a sculptors studio in Rome. Following this evidently potent impulse, he recast the unfinished play into blank verse and painfully completed it, with what he called scarcely justifiable transfusions of my own blood. What the connection was between modelling and the decision to take up again a long abandoned and extraordinarily difficult project, he did not say; but perhaps one may speculate. While his hands shaped the formless, malleable clay, may he not have wondered about the radical and dismaying difference between the sculptors medium and his own: between clay-or marble, pigment, tones-and words? For the difference is radical. All other artists have for their medium what Aristotle called a material cause: more or less shapeless, always meaningless matter, upon which they can imprint form and meaning. Their media become media proper only under their hands; through shaping they communicate. As artists they are uniquely sovereign, minting unminted bullion into currency, stamping their image upon it. The poet is denied this creative sovereignty. His material cause is a medium before he starts to fashion it; he must deal in an already current and largely defaced coinage. In fact it is not even a coinage, but rather a paper currency. Words, as the poet finds them, are tokens for real things, which they are


American Political Science Review | 1960

On Reading Ordinary Prose: A Reply to Allan Bloom

Sigurd Burckhardt

There is no help for it: after taking Allan Bloom to task for reading Shakespeare badly and tyrannically, I must now charge him with doing no better by me. I cannot join the debate at the elevated level he prefers-the level where one can talk about art, life and political philosophy. Since the original issue was the validity or invalidity of his and Harry Jaffas Shakespeare interpretations-and since his rebuttal raises questions about what I did and did not say-he must forgive me for staying closer to the text than he will like. Perhaps, in return for the lesson he has given me in political philosophy, he will accept one in the much humbler discipline of reading. But first I must try to mollify him over the injustice he feels I did him when I empaneled my imaginary jury. He writes: In presenting my conclusions, I have a right to ask that they be tested in the light of my evidence and my arguments [his italics]. If I had known that he was writing syllogisms rather than an Othello interpretation, I would have been more careful; I thought that he, like any other interpreter, was to be judged by the evidence and by the ordinary rules of inference. As I see it, only the conclusion of a syllogism can be adequately tested as Bloom demands that his be tested. In an interpretation the interpreters own evidence may be insufficient or distorted; the argument may neglect contrary evidence, or it may impose constructions which the -evidence is not strong enough to bear. Moreover-and more directly to Mr. Blooms point-since the conclusions are in fact descriptions (however refined) of the object of interpretation, their unrecognisability creates a strong presumption that the interpretation which brought them forth is invalid. As for the jury, I submit that merely by the act of publication Bloom presented his case to just such a jury as I assumed; that he does so again now; and that I am doing the same. If I committed an error in dramatising this simple fact, it was at most that of laboring the obvious. I prefer to pass over the various characterizations by which Bloom sees fit to insult this jury. My description of it was simple and clear: widely read, intelligent men. I should be glad to know what canons of debate he subscribes to, when he willfully distorts the character of a jury which he then attacks me for having summoned. The jury he complains about is quite of his own selection. But to the work Bloom has cut out for me. He says sternly: In the first place, it is not true that Jaffa is unaware that there is a subplot [in Lear]. (p. 458) This, I suppose, would be called a leading assertion: if I agree to it, I am damned; if I disagree, I am demonstrably in the wrong. The only answer I have is that I never said anything of the sort; I am just as positive as Bloom is that Jaffa knew of the subplots existence. On the page Bloom cites, I use the words this unawareness, but the antecedent sentence, to which they unambiguously refer, reads as follows: It does not occur to [Jaffa] that his whole elaborate edifice is undermined by no more than the simple fact that it renders the patterned interweaving of the two plots meaningless. This is a puny matter; I mention it only because it is symptomatic of Blooms mode of reading texts. In a final note, he requires me, if I am not merely being pedantic, to show him what error he has made by not citing what recent Othello critics have produced and marketed (the phrasing casts a revealing light on his mode of argumentation). I will oblige him, not by showing him an error now, but simply by quoting what I wrote in this context and what he therefore had in front of him when he made this demand. After citing his original article to the effect that Othello criticism has tended to forget the problem of how the hero falls so readily into Jagos snares, I continue: Had Bloom consulted-to name only oneRobert Heilmans full-length study ... he would have discovered a very careful treatment of this problem. Indeed, Othello criticism has lately been almost obsessed with [it]. Does he require any further information about the error he has made? It was he who charged critics with having tended to forget a problem which he claims to have confronted and solved. My very simple point was that the charge was untrue and the claim correspondingly doubtful. But I find it hard to remain calm about more important matters. He imputes to me (p. 463) a conventional morality so primitive that it leads me to believe that Jago is a bad man, and Othello is a good man, and nothing more need (or may) be said. Has he any warrant to ascribe to me this absurdly simple-minded belief-a belief which he then makes it his equally simple task to demolish? I did not impute opinions to him; I quoted him, and the quote speaks


ELH | 1961

Tristram Shandy's Law of Gravity

Sigurd Burckhardt


ELH | 1966

King John: The Ordering of this Present Time

Sigurd Burckhardt


ELH | 1962

The Merchant of Venice: The Gentle Bond

Sigurd Burckhardt


The Hudson Review | 1961

The Poetry of Hugo von Hofmannsthal

Sigurd Burckhardt; Hugo von Hofmannsthal; Michael Hamburger; John Bednall; Arthur Davidson; John Mander; Christopher Middleton; Stephen Spender; Vernon Watkins


The Hudson Review | 1966

German Made Easy

Sigurd Burckhardt; Erich Heller


The Hudson Review | 1964

The Limits of Representation

Sigurd Burckhardt; Rolf Hochhuth; Richard Winston; Clara Winston


The German Quarterly | 1963

Egmont and Prinz Friedrich von Homburg: Expostulation and Reply

Sigurd Burckhardt

Collaboration


Dive into the Sigurd Burckhardt's collaboration.

Researchain Logo
Decentralizing Knowledge