Yaroslav Shramko
Pedagogical University
Network
Latest external collaboration on country level. Dive into details by clicking on the dots.
Publication
Featured researches published by Yaroslav Shramko.
Journal of Philosophical Logic | 2005
Yaroslav Shramko; Heinrich Wansing
In Belnap’s useful 4-valued logic, the set 2={T,F} of classical truth values is generalized to the set 4=℘(2)={∅,{T},{F},{T,F}}. In the present paper, we argue in favor of extending this process to the set 16=℘(4) (and beyond). It turns out that this generalization is well-motivated and leads from the bilattice FOUR2 with an information and a truth-and-falsity ordering to another algebraic structure, namely the trilattice SIXTEEN3 with an information ordering together with a truth ordering and a (distinct) falsity ordering. Interestingly, the logics generated separately by the algebraic operations under the truth order and under the falsity order in SIXTEEN3 coincide with the logic of FOUR2, namely first degree entailment. This observation may be taken as a further indication of the significance of first degree entailment. In the present setting, however, it becomes rather natural to consider also logical systems in the language obtained by combining the vocabulary of the logic of the truth order and the falsity order. We semantically define the logics of the two orderings in the extended language and in both cases axiomatize a certain fragment comprising three unary operations: a negation, an involution, and their combination. We also suggest two other definitions of logics in the full language, including a bi-consequence system. In other words, in addition to presenting first degree entailment as a useful 16-valued logic, we define further useful 16-valued logics for reasoning about truth and (non-)falsity. We expect these logics to be an interesting and useful instrument in information processing, especially when we deal with a net of hierarchically interconnected computers. We also briefly discuss Arieli’s and Avron’s notion of a logical bilattice and state a number of open problems for future research.
Journal of Logic, Language and Information | 2006
Yaroslav Shramko; Heinrich Wansing
In Philosophical Logic, the Liar Paradox has been used to motivate the introduction of both truth value gaps and truth value gluts. Moreover, in the light of “revenge Liar” arguments, also higher-order combinations of generalized truth values have been suggested to account for so-called hyper-contradictions. In the present paper, Graham Priests treatment of generalized truth values is scrutinized and compared with another strategy of generalizing the set of classical truth values and defining an entailment relation on the resulting sets of higher-order values. This method is based on the concept of a multilattice. If the method is applied to the set of truth values of Belnaps “useful four-valued logic”, one obtains a trilattice, and, more generally, structures here called Belnap-trilattices. As in Priests case, it is shown that the generalized truth values motivated by hyper-contradictions have no effect on the logic. Whereas Priests construction in terms of designated truth values always results in his Logic of Paradox, the present construction in terms of truth and falsity orderings always results in First Degree Entailment. However, it is observed that applying the multilattice-approach to Priests initial set of truth values leads to an interesting algebraic structure of a “bi-and-a-half” lattice which determines seven-valued logics different from Priests Logic of Paradox.
Studia Logica | 2005
Yaroslav Shramko
We consider a logic which is semantically dual (in some precise sense of the term) to intuitionistic. This logic can be labeled as “falsification logic”: it embodies the Popperian methodology of scientific discovery. Whereas intuitionistic logic deals with constructive truth and non-constructive falsity, and Nelsons logic takes both truth and falsity as constructive notions, in the falsification logic truth is essentially non-constructive as opposed to falsity that is conceived constructively. We also briefly clarify the relationships of our falsification logic to some other logical systems.
Studia Logica | 2008
Heinrich Wansing; Yaroslav Shramko
AbstractAccording to Suszko’s Thesis, there are but two logical values, true and false. In this paper, R. Suszko’s, G. Malinowski’s, and M. Tsuji’s analyses of logical twovaluedness are critically discussed. Another analysis is presented, which favors a notion of a logical system as encompassing possibly more than one consequence relation. [A] fundamental problem concerning many-valuedness is to know what it really is.[13, p. 281]
Archive | 2012
Yaroslav Shramko; Heinrich Wansing
As another example, let’s write a function that plays around with truth and falsehood. It would be nice to make a function that will give us the third thing in a letter or sentence. What should we do if the sequence is too short? As an arbitrary choice, let’s have it return #f. There are several different ways of writing this sort of function. (The book points out this sort of thing in its discussion on “function vs process.”) First, let’s try it with the if special form.
Archive | 2016
Yaroslav Shramko
This paper highlights the importance of a strategy for semantic analysis initiated by J. Michael Dunn, known in the literature as the “American Plan.” The key insight of the plan relies on allowing under-determined and over-determined logical valuations, which prove to be essential for a logical analysis of information structures. The main directions in the development of this fundamental idea are explained, and an implementation of the possible generalization thereof is briefly reviewed, culminating in the notion of a multi-consequence logic.
Studia Logica | 2009
Yaroslav Shramko; Heinrich Wansing
The famous “slingshot argument” developed by Church, Gödel, Quine and Davidson is often considered to be a formally strict proof of the Fregean conception that all true sentences, as well as all false ones, have one and the same denotation, namely their corresponding truth value: the true or the false. In this paper we examine the analysis of the slingshot argument by means of a non-Fregean logic undertaken recently by A.Wóitowicz and put to the test her claim that the slingshot argument is in fact circular and presupposes what it intends to prove. We show that this claim is untenable. Nevertheless, the language of non-Fregean logic can serve as a useful tool for representing the slingshot argument, and several versions of the slingshot argument in non-Fregean logics are presented. In particular, a new version of the slingshot argument is presented, which can be circumvented neither by an appeal to a Russellian theory of definite descriptions nor by resorting to an analogous “Russellian” theory of λ–terms.
Studia Logica | 2017
Norihiro Kamide; Yaroslav Shramko; Heinrich Wansing
In this paper, bi-intuitionistic multilattice logic, which is a combination of multilattice logic and the bi-intuitionistic logic also known as Heyting–Brouwer logic, is introduced as a Gentzen-type sequent calculus. A Kripke semantics is developed for this logic, and the completeness theorem with respect to this semantics is proved via theorems for embedding this logic into bi-intuitionistic logic. The logic proposed is an extension of first-degree entailment logic and can be regarded as a bi-intuitionistic variant of the original classical multilattice logic determined by the algebraic structure of multilattices. Similar completeness and embedding results are also shown for another logic called bi-intuitionistic connexive multilattice logic, obtained by replacing the connectives of intuitionistic implication and co-implication with their connexive variants.
Logica Universalis | 2017
Norihiro Kamide; Yaroslav Shramko
A modal extension of multilattice logic, called modal multilattice logic, is introduced as a Gentzen-type sequent calculus
Studia Logica | 2017
Yaroslav Shramko; D. D. Zaitsev; Alexander Belikov