Jacob Hoeksema
University of Groningen
Network
Latest external collaboration on country level. Dive into details by clicking on the dots.
Publication
Featured researches published by Jacob Hoeksema.
Natural Language and Linguistic Theory | 1983
Jacob Hoeksema
Summary and ConclusionsIn this paper I have given a rather simple and, I believe, elegant semantics for the comparative,No account has been given of NP-comparatives involving measure noun phrases as in Susan is taller than five foot. See Klein (1980: 27ff.) for an excellent discussion. which explains the distribution of certain negative polarity items and correctly predicts the validity of inferences concerning comparatives. It was argued that a distinction has to be made between NP-comparatives and S-comparatives, in order to capture the very different semantic properties of these two constructions. In this respect the present paper differs from previous treatments of the semantics of the comparative, such as Cresswell (1976) and Klein (1980). According to the theory presented above, the comparative adjective denotes a Boolean homomorphism in the NP-comparative construction (just like all extensional transitive verbs), but it denotes an anti-additive function in the S-construction.The semantics for the S-comparative shares some basic features with the semantic analysis of the comparative in Klein (1980). It differs, however, in that grading relations have been introduced here as primitive notions, whereas Klein proposed to explain them away by a suitable theory of contextual interpretation of positive adjective. By introducing grading relations as primitive notions, I have been able to simplify the semantics for the S-comparative to a considerable degree. However, a Klein-style theory of context could be placed on top of the present theory, if one wanted to do so. The present paper also differs from the contributions by Cresswell and Klein in that it does not provide an explicit syntax to complement the semantics. I have refrained from giving a fragment in the style of Montague-grammar, because I felt that I did not have anything substantial to contribute there.The semantics for the S-comparative provided here can account for the possibility of the Dutch negative polarity item ook maar occurring in the S-comparative (though not in the NP-comparative). There were two reasons for focussing on ook maar: first, it calls our attention to an important logical property of the S-comparative, viz. its anti-additivity, and, secondly, it points out an area where Ladusaws theory of negative polarity needs further elaboration, to wit, the differences in distribution that are found among the various negative polarity items, as illustrated here by the Dutch examples ook maar and hoeven (cf. (45) above). Still a lot of work, even on the basic level of description, has to be done in this area, but the progress made so far by Ladusaw (1979) and Zwarts (1981, to appear) at least warrants the expectation that this work will not be without its rewards. These works also show that the model-theoretic approach to semantics is especially well-suited to giving an explanatory account of polarity phenomena. I hope that the present paper may help to convince those who still hold that formal semantics is irrelevant for linguistic purposes.
Journal of Linguistics | 1993
Jacob Hoeksema; Donna Jo Napoli
The contrast between subordination and co-ordination, from both a syntactic viewpoint and a semantic viewpoint, is assumed by most formal theories of grammar today, so much so that generally only avowed a-formalists or anti-formalists seriously entertain the possibility that any other type of relationship may exist between clauses. Yet paratactic constructions persist in nagging us, undermining precisely that contrast, sometimes competing with co-ordination, sometimes with subordination, for the same semantic niche in language. In this article we focus on one such case in English, that of complex sentences containing the degree-adverbs so or such in which one clause serves to indicate an extent to which the predicate modified by so/such holds and the other clause expresses a result. As we argue below, there are two types of complex sentences with this general characterization, one of which is of the paratactic kind and is exemplified in (I):
John Benjamins Publishers | 2001
Jacob Hoeksema
Journal of Semantics | 1991
Jacob Hoeksema; Frans Zwarts
Perspectives on Negation and Polarity Items | 2001
Jacob Hoeksema; A. van der Wouden; V Sánchez Valencia; Hotze Rullmann
Linguistic Analysis | 1996
Jacob Hoeksema; E.H. Klein-van der Laaken
Berkeley Linguistics Society | 1994
Jacob Hoeksema
Quantifiers, logic, and language. | 1996
Jacob Hoeksema; J.M. van der Does; J. van Eijck
Linguistics and Philosophy | 1991
Jacob Hoeksema
Journal of Linguistics | 1999
Jacob Hoeksema