John Schwenkler
Mount St. Mary's University
Network
Latest external collaboration on country level. Dive into details by clicking on the dots.
Publication
Featured researches published by John Schwenkler.
Philosophical Explorations | 2011
John Schwenkler
According to G.E.M. Anscombe, an agents knowledge of his own intentional actions differs from his knowledge of his unintended behaviors as well as the knowledge others can have of what he intentionally does, in being known “without observation”. I begin by posing a problem for any conception of this theory according to which non-observational knowledge must be independent of sense perception, and criticize several recent attempts to get around the problem. Having done this, I develop an alternative account of non-observational knowledge according to which it consists in the particular causal role of an agents self-awareness in bringing his intentional actions about.
Journal of Moral Philosophy | 2018
John Schwenkler
A philosophical account of self-knowledge should offer more than an epistemological explanation of first-personal privilege. It should also address the many cases where the first-person perspective is not so privileged, and account for the importance of self-knowledge to a person’s social and psychological well-being. Quassim Cassam’s Self-Knowledge for Humans and John Doris’s Talking to Our Selves both emphasize the importance of these latter tasks, but neither author is wholly successful: Cassam’s argument rests on a gross distortion of the “Rationalist” picture he sets up as a foil, and Doris’s on a skeptical argument that stands in some questionable company.
Canadian Journal of Philosophy | 2018
Eric Marcus; John Schwenkler
ABSTRACT We argue that honesty in assertion requires non-empirical knowledge that what one asserts is what one believes. Our argument proceeds from the thought that to assert honestly, one must follow and not merely conform to the norm ‘Assert that p only if you believe that p’. Furthermore, careful consideration of cases shows that the sort of doxastic self-knowledge required for following this norm cannot be acquired on the basis of observation, inference, or any other form of detection of one’s own doxastic states. It is, as we put it, transparent rather than empirical self-knowledge.
Australasian Journal of Philosophy | 2017
John Schwenkler
tion and knowledge acquisition (for example, Pickav e and Shapiro [2012]). Especially when dealing with Locke, De Pierris would need to consider recent works in the history and philosophy of science that explicitly argue against her own view, in that they acknowledge Locke as an important proponent of Newtonianism who offered invaluable contributions to the establishment of a new experimental practice [Gaukroger 2009; Anstey 2011; Domski 2012]. Works that raise questions about Newton’s own metaphysical commitments and/or directly challenge De Pierris’s previously published works in which she defends a similar account are not discussed either (for example, Janiak [2007] and Biener and Schliesser [2014]). In general, the literature discussed and referenced in De Perris’s book is rather old, and debates flagged as recent are not recent at all. All of this leads to the impression that her account, which is in fact supposed to be presenting a novel reading of Hume, unfolds without taking on board important developments within the scholarly debate.
Cognitive Science | 2015
Robert E. Briscoe; John Schwenkler
Analysis | 2013
John Schwenkler
I-perception | 2012
John Schwenkler
Philosophical Studies | 2013
John Schwenkler
Noûs | 2014
John Schwenkler
Philosophy Compass | 2012
John Schwenkler