Matthew McGrath
University of Missouri
Network
Latest external collaboration on country level. Dive into details by clicking on the dots.
Publication
Featured researches published by Matthew McGrath.
Synthese | 2007
Matthew McGrath
Much of the plausibility of epistemic conservatism derives from its prospects of explaining our rationality in holding memory beliefs. In the first two parts of this paper, I argue for the inadequacy of the two standard approaches to the epistemology of memory beliefs, preservationism and evidentialism. In the third, I point out the advantages of the conservative approach and consider how well conservatism survives three of the strongest objections against it. Conservatism does survive, I claim, but only if qualified in certain ways. Appropriately qualified, conservatism is no longer the powerful anti-skeptical tool some have hoped for, but a doctrine closely connected with memory.
Australasian Journal of Philosophy | 2005
Matthew McGrath
One familiar form of argument for rejecting entities of a certain kind is that, by rejecting them, we avoid certain difficult problems associated with them. Such problem-avoidance arguments backfire if the problems cited survive the elimination of the rejected entities. In particular, we examine one way problems can survive: a question for the realist about which of a set of inconsistent statements is false may give way to an equally difficult question for the eliminativist about which of a set of inconsistent statements fail to be ‘factual’. Much of the first half of the paper is devoted to explaining a notion of factuality that does not imply truth but still consists in ‘getting the world right’. The second half of the paper is a case study. Some ‘compositional nihilists’ have argued that, by rejecting composite objects (and so by denying the composition ever takes place), we avoid the notorious puzzles of coincidence, for example, the statue/lump and the ship of Theseus puzzles. Using the apparatus developed in the first half of the paper, we explore the question of whether these puzzles survive the elimination of composite objects.
Philosophical Studies | 2003
Matthew McGrath
This paper argues, in response to Huw Price, that deflationism has theresources to account for the normativity of truth. The discussioncenters on a principle of hyper-objective assertibility, that one isincorrect to assert that p if not-p. If this principle doesn’t statea fact about truth, it needn’t be explained by deflationists. If itdoes, it can be explained.
The Philosophical Review | 2017
Matthew McGrath
Walking through the supermarket, I see the avocados. I haven’t seen any labels. I don’t need to. I know those are avocados. Context might provide some hints. However, it hardly primes me to expect avocados in the very place I’m looking. In other cases, there are fewer hints. In April, I place a pumpkin on my office desk. The next time a colleague stops in to talk with me she sees it. She knows it is a pumpkin, even if she’s puzzled about why it’s there. In these cases, it doesn’t seem to the perceiver like he or she is performing any reasoning. It seems as if one sees the thing and straightaway knows what it is. J. L. Austin describes the phenomenology well in a memorable example. If I see pig-like marks or find buckets of pig food, I have evidence an animal is a pig. But if the animal “emerges and stands there plainly in view, there is no longer any question of collecting evidence; its coming into view doesn’t provide me with more evidence that it’s a pig, I can now just see that it is, the question is settled” (Austin 1962, 115). In cases in which the phenomenology is of this “just see” sort, it’s unsurprising that many epistemologists would conclude that the knowl-
Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines | 2016
Matthew McGrath
Abstract Stewart Cohen offers a critique of much contemporary epistemology. Epistemologies use the term ‘epistemic’ in order to specify the issues they investigate and about which they disagree. Cohen sees widespread confusion about these issues. The problem, he argues, is that ‘epistemic’ is functioning as an inadequately defined technical term. I will argue, rather, that the troubles come more from non-technical vocabulary, in particular with ‘justification’ and ‘ought’, and generally from the difficulty of explaining normativity. Overall, the message of this paper is that normativity is what’s hard to understand, not the term ‘epistemic.’
Synthese | 2018
Matthew McGrath
In recent work, Sosa proposes a comprehensive account of epistemic value based on an axiology for attempts. According to this axiology, an attempt is better if it succeeds, better still if it is apt (i.e., succeeds through competence), and best if it is fully apt, (i.e., guided to aptness by apt beliefs that it would be apt). Beliefs are understood as attempts aiming at the truth. Thus, a belief is better if true, better still if apt, and best if fully apt. I raise a Kantian obstacle for Sosa’s account, arguing that the quality or worth of an attempt is independent of whether it succeeds. In particular, an attempt can be fully worthy despite being a failure. I then consider whether Sosa’s competence-theoretic framework provides the resources for an axiology of attempts that does not place so much weight on success. I discuss the most promising candidate, an axiology grounded in the competence of attempts, or what Sosa calls adroitness. An adroit attempt may fail. I raise doubts about whether an adroitness-based axiology can provide a plausible explanation of the worthiness of subjects’ beliefs in epistemically unfortunate situations, such as the beliefs of the brain in a vat. I conclude by speculating that the notion of a belief’s fit with what the subject has to go on, a notion missing from Sosa’s competence-theoretic framework, is crucial to explaining epistemic worth.
Archive | 2013
Matthew McGrath; Jeremy Fantl
In Sect. 1 of this chapter, Matthew McGrath examines Sosa’s work on the nature of truth. Sosa’s chief purpose is to determine what sort of theory of truth is appropriate for “truth-centered epistemology” – an epistemology that takes truth to be the goal of inquiry and which explains key epistemic notions in terms of truth. While Sosa refutes arguments from Putnam and Davidson against the correspondence theory, he is hesitant to endorse it because he doubts we have a clear enough grasp of what correspondence amounts to and what the correspondents are. A truth-centered epistemologist, however, is free to work with minimalism about truth and Moorean primitivism. Part of Sosa’s case for primitivism, and against minimalism, involves a comparison with Moore’s account of goodness. Here McGrath notes an important dissimilarity between the two (i.e., susceptibility to “open-question” arguments) and suggests that this may be reason to prefer minimalism to primitivism.
Archive | 2009
Jeremy Fantl; Matthew McGrath
The Philosophical Review | 2002
Jeremy Fantl; Matthew McGrath
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research | 2007
Jeremy Fantl; Matthew McGrath