Richard Foley
University of Notre Dame
Network
Latest external collaboration on country level. Dive into details by clicking on the dots.
Publication
Featured researches published by Richard Foley.
Archive | 2009
Richard Foley
The two accounts would seem to be close cousins. An account of rational degrees of belief simply takes a more fine-grained approach than does an account of rational beliefs. The latter classifies belief-like attitudes into a threefold scheme of believing, disbelieving, and withholding judgment, whereas the former introduces as many distinctions as needed to talk about the levels of confidence one has in various propositions.
Noûs | 1992
Richard Foley
Suppose that your degree of belief in p is twice as great as your degree of belief in its negation, while your degree of belief in q is the same as its negation. Suppose also that p implies q. Since a proposition cannot be more probable than a proposition it implies, your degrees of belief violate one of the rules of the probability calculus; they are probabilistically incoherent. If you post odds that reflect these incoherent degrees of belief-i.e., if you post 2:1 odds on the truth of p and 1:1 odds on the truth of q-you will be vulnerable to a Dutch book, which is to say that your opponent can make a series of bets against you such that you will suffer a net loss, no matter how the events you are betting on turn out. For instance, your opponent can bet
Archive | 1990
Richard Foley
1.50 on the truth of q and
The Philosophical Review | 1987
Hilary Kornblith; Richard Foley
1 on the falsity of p. If q is true, you will lose
The Philosophical Review | 1995
Richard Fumerton; Richard Foley
1.50 on q. You still could win the
The Monist | 1985
Richard Foley
1 bet on p, but even if you do, you will suffer a net loss of
Philosophical Studies | 1985
Richard Foley; Richard Fumerton
.50. On the other hand, if q is false, you will win
Analysis | 1991
Richard Foley
1.50 from your opponents bet on q. But since p implies q, p is also false. So, you will lose
Archive | 2005
Richard Foley
2 to your opponent on p. Thus, once again you will suffer a net loss. This result can be generalized. It can be proved that if your degrees of belief violate the probability calculus and you are willing to post odds that reflect your degrees of belief, then a skillful enough opponent can make a Dutch book against you. (Ramsey, 1964; Definetti, 1964) This makes it tempting to infer that it is always irrational to have incoherent degrees of belief. And in fact, many philosophers have inferred that this is always irrational. But it is important to note that there is no proof of this latter claim.1 There is no proof even if we assume that it is always irrational for you to make yourself vulnerable to a Dutch book. For even with this assumption, what follows is that it is irrational to accept bets at odds that reflect your degrees of belief when these degrees are incoherent. What degree of confidence it is rational for you to have in a proposition is one matter, what odds if any it is rational for you post on it is another.2
Archive | 2008
Richard Foley
Skeptical hypotheses have been allowed to set the terms of the epistemological debate. They convince no one. Yet they have an enormous influence. It is often influence by provocation. They provoke epistemologists into endorsing metaphysical and linguistic positions that antecedently would have seemed to have had little appeal. Skeptical hypotheses, it is said, cannot even be meaningfully asserted, or if they can, the nature of God or the nature of objects or the nature of thought makes it altogether impossible for them to be true. There are those who refuse to be provoked, but even their epistemologies tend to be dominated by skeptical hypotheses. The hypotheses push them into an overly defensive posture from which it can seem that the test of an epistemology is how well it would fare in a hostile environment. There must be a third way. There must be a way to think about skeptical hypotheses that is neither dismissive nor submissive.